![[personal profile]](https://www.dreamwidth.org/img/silk/identity/user.png)
Once upon a time, boccaderlupo recommended Sallustius' On the Gods and the World to me as a short introduction to Neoplatonism. But where he found it clear, I found it obscure! (I believe I described it to him as "a puzzle-box"—it seems to me that all the pieces fit together elegantly, but one needs to know the trick to open it up and get at the candy inside, and not knowing the trick all I could do was to play with it for a while before setting it down again.) Yesterday, I suggested perhaps starting up some discussion on the topic in the hopes that, with the help of other blind men, I might discover that this rope I'm touching is actually an elephant.
Therefore, I plan to post a chapter of the text each week (on Wednesday, in honor of the lord of dialogue), and perhaps we can unpack it together. I will only be posting the text in the subject post, and placing whatever thoughts and questions I may have down in the comments: after all, I am a student here rather than a lecturer, and anyway it might be helpful to break up discussion into parallel threads to keep things organized. Anyone is welcome to lurk, comment, ask their own questions, etc. I'll be transcribing from Gilbert Murray's 1925 translation, though I also have Thomas Taylor's 1793 translation handy and will call it out when there's something interesting. (Our good Br'er Wolf recommended Arthur Nock's 1926 translation, but I don't have a copy. It'll be in the public domain in a couple months, though, so perhaps we can revisit it then.)
Let's pick the puzzle-box up, shall we?
I. What the Disciple should be; and concerning Common Conceptions.
Those who wish to hear about the Gods should have been well guided from childhood, and not habituated to foolish beliefs. They should also be in disposition good and sensible, that they may properly attend to the teaching.
They ought also to know the Common Conceptions. Common Conceptions are those to which all men agree as soon as they are asked; for instance, that all God is good, free from passion,* free from change. For whatever suffers change does so for the worse or the better; if for the worse, it is made bad; if for the better, it must have been bad at first.
* Thomas Taylor's translation gives "without passivity." Arthur Darby Nock's gives "impassive."
no subject
Date: 2021-11-03 01:03 pm (UTC)no subject
Date: 2021-11-03 06:35 pm (UTC)In terms of the "hierarchy," as it were, you have, per Iamblichus: gods, archangels, angels, daemons (more akin to spirits, not necessarily in the pejorative), heroes, archons, and us mortals.
Axé
no subject
Date: 2021-11-04 12:24 am (UTC)no subject
Date: 2021-11-04 01:18 am (UTC)Axé
no subject
Date: 2021-11-04 01:55 am (UTC)no subject
Date: 2021-11-04 03:54 pm (UTC)..and many thanks to the host & commentariat of this worthy exploration!
no subject
Date: 2021-11-04 03:56 pm (UTC)Alexander Wilder's translation is at the Twilit Grotto.
no subject
Date: 2021-11-07 01:00 am (UTC)perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-03 09:05 pm (UTC)Our conversing with the Gods (or not) does imply a change in state, but it's a change in *our* state, not in theirs. Their providence is always present, but we can change to become more or less receptive.
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-03 11:41 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-04 12:21 am (UTC)But if a god is changeless, then they are unable to receive information of any kind (for the reason Sallustius and you describe), which means that we're not conversing. Perhaps they are speaking, but it would have to be a one-way transfer of information, right?
This implies to me that the gods are so far beyond comprehension (indeed, beyond comprehensibility) that I'm not even sure I can begin to make sense of them. (Though perhaps we'll see once we're a bit further into the text!) Certainly, the gods we're talking about don't fit my model for "gods" (which I suppose I have always assumed to be "vast people"). This harkens back to the conversation above, what are those Common Conceptions people had back in Sallustius' time? I assume this means they had a very different understanding of what the word "god" meant than I do?
In any case, I'm very thankful for the lower orders of beings who I can at least interact with! They may not be "gods" in Sallustius' sense, but I am not sure how I would be sustained without them!
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-04 01:28 am (UTC)While I am not privy to the interactions you speak of and therefore cannot judge, I conjecture that you are interacting with the “intelligible” aspect of certain gods—the aspect that manifests in some way that can be apprehended by mortals. Proclus lays out in some detail the distinctions between intellective, intelligible-intellective, and intelligible gods, but this is where things get heavy and tricky for me, as the language becomes highly technical.
For my purposes, I would say the entities we feel familiar with are—barring us being hoodwinked by malign forces, gods forbid—the aspects of a god that they have chosen to unveil to us in some limited way.
Axé
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-04 06:21 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-04 09:08 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-06 05:38 pm (UTC)The Christians synthesized this idea with their conception of God, via Pseudo-Dionysius. Thus God the Father bears many of the attributes one would associate with "The One." Pagan Neoplatonists, on the other hands, would extend these qualities across the spectrum of divine beings, who abide at the pinnacle of the cosmos, ontologically speaking.
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-08 06:21 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-08 11:26 pm (UTC)When it comes to the gods, all of us can only know so much.
Axé
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-07 01:28 am (UTC)The first sentence has "the Gods" in the plural. That means exactly what we'd expect.
Later, in the bit about "common conceptions" (which Nock translates, perhaps more helpfully, as "universal opinions," in other words, beliefs shared by everyone), the Greek uses a grammatically singular construction, hoti pas theos agathos, hoti apathēs, hoti ametablētos. The key term here is pas. Taylor (as quoted in the post) renders pas as "all." Really, this term is a universal quantifier, so while "all" is fine, a more felicitous translation could be "every" or "any" in the sense of "any imaginable, any possible."
So the entire phrase means: "that every God is good, and impassive, and unchangeable." That preserves the grammatical singular of the Greek; we could just as well convey the same idea using the plural in English: "that all Gods are good, and impassive, and unchangeable."
Even in other contexts where the word "all/every" is not given, Sallustius and his fellow pagan Platonists would only use the singular form theos in one of two ways: (1) in a context where an individual God (perhaps Zeus or Dionysos) was already referred to by name, and they were just mentioning that same God again without repeating his name, or (2) as a generic singular to refer to the class, in just the way that someone might say "Man is the measure of all things" or "man is a rational animal," thereby referring to human beings universally or in general, without in any way implying that there's only one.
(In Greek, unlike in English, you use the definite article—"the" (ho)—in both those constructions (ho theos, ho anthrōpos) to refer to the class or the generic. It's a usage that, because of Christianity, is almost impossible to convey any more in English. Sigh.)
Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-08 06:23 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2021-11-08 06:40 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2022-03-01 09:47 pm (UTC)Re: perfect, therefore unchanging
Date: 2022-03-02 12:33 am (UTC)I'm still pretty much in the dark, but it's interesting to hear what those more in the know have to say about the gods.
the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-04 08:37 pm (UTC)The knowledge likewise of common conceptions is necessary; but common conceptions are such things as all men, when interrogated, acknowledge to be indubitably certain; such as, that every god is good, without passivity, and free from all mutation; for every thing which is changed, is either changed into something better or into something worse: and if into something worse, it will become depraved, but if into something better, it must have been evil in the beginning.
This section is where my attention falls most squarely each time I read this chapter. First, I read the proposition about gods in two directions.
1. The gods are ___. A simple description of the characteristics of the divine beings we call gods.
2. That which is ___, ___, and ___ can be categorized as gods.
I know that this is not exactly what Sallustius is saying, but it's an interesting conceptual exercise to think of it via mode 2: that which we recognize as good, active, and unchanging(ly so) can be conceived of as a god. I think this supports Sallustius's later assertion (Ch. 4) that myths/fables work on different levels and that the gods and their actions can be understood differently via those levels.
Second, I've tried to accept S.'s limited notion of change, but my contrary-mary-mind insists on chiming in. I don't think change must be forced onto an axis of better-worse. Acorn - oak, child - adult, summer - autumn, even living - dead... Perhaps it's helpful to consider that there are non-polarized types of changes that do not change the "essential nature" of a thing (I feel like I'm walking among landmines by using that phrasing, but I don't know what else to say). So, a being may arise, grow, develop, mature, decline - but its essential nature is unchanging? I may be over-expanding the concept of change here since I'm not just talking about gods... but perhaps you see the dilemma. I don't see change as indicative of a flaw. Gods may not appear to us to change, but who's to say that they don't change on some cosmic level. Their stories change - does that mean it's only the humans who've changed their conceptions?
I'm also seeing if I can reconcile JMG's notion that gods may in fact be part of an "ecosystem" and may have periods of increasing/decreasing influence. If they don't change, then nope. If, though, they change but without modification of their essential natures as divine beings, then maybe?
I admit, I don't have a clue. But those are questions that occur to me.
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-04 08:59 pm (UTC)I suspect that Sallustius is even using "god" as a term of art, here. Apuleius seems to clearly treat "the Moon is a god" as a "Common Conception:"
But I suspect what Apuleius means by "god" is not what Sallustius means by "god." (It's also worth noting that Apuleius predates Sallustius by a couple hundred years; indeed he predates Neoplatonism. So I suspect we're dealing with a special set of notions peculiar to Neoplatonism, which are not quite clear to me.)
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-04 09:07 pm (UTC)Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-04 09:10 pm (UTC)Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-04 09:17 pm (UTC)gee, how do we a) figure out what they each mean by "god" and b) figure out what we mean by it?! :D
Maybe be reverting back to my reversed reading mentioned above?: that which is good, active, and unchanging...
hmmm....
also, good point about Moon as god/dess of change. More hmmm...
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-08 11:29 pm (UTC)Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-07 02:38 am (UTC)Let's remember that "passive" is the antonym of "active." The critical claim is that the Gods are always agents or actors—those who initiate activity—and they are never "patients" in the sense of having anything done *to* them.
This means that the only relevant causal factor (using that term somewhat loosely) that accounts for why a God is the way he is, is the God himself. There is not, nor could there ever be, any appeal to any causes apart from the God to explain the God.
Everything that a God is, he always is, because of his own nature and his own eternal activity. Because the God is entirely active, never passive, and the God is always present to himself, then all the causes that would explain the God's being a certain way always and eternally present: the God himself is the one and only such cause. And so every way that a God can be, he will always be, since there is no change in causes that would give rise to different effects/results.
Therefore, because every God is both good and impassive, there's nothing that a particular God could be that he isn't already.
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-07 02:05 pm (UTC)Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-07 03:34 pm (UTC)In the case of my above example of the Moon, She is not definitionally a God, since She is acted upon (by the actions of light, gravity, mechanical action, and who-knows-what else) by the Sun, Jupiter, Venus, the great Gods above, the engineers of the Apollo program, and even—in a minuscule way!—by little old me.
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-07 05:18 pm (UTC)Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-08 08:44 pm (UTC)Note that later in this same tract, Sallustius will emphasize that (in his view) the celestial bodies are not themselves gods per se, but rather, if I remember right, vehicles for the gods' activities. He contrasts this with, if memory serves, the Egyptian view, in which (according to him) the "planets" are equated with the gods themselves.
For myself, I tend to regard the heavenly bodies as massive sunthemata (tokens) that serve as the most potent and visible conduits for the gods' expression, thus their outsized (literally and figuratively) impact on the events here in the sublunar world. This is just my person opinion, however.
On how divination and various rites impact (or rather, fail to impact) the gods, who are immutable, I would consult Iamblichus, though I think Sallustius touches on it briefly, as well.
Axé
Re: the nature of change
Date: 2021-11-09 02:41 pm (UTC)